- Home
- Paul J Croce
Young William James Thinking Page 5
Young William James Thinking Read online
Page 5
come of age. His young adulthood was a time of both personal crises and intellectual
and cultural explorations.
16 Young William James Thinking
assumes a dualist question: Did he favor science or religion? In 1878 he
addressed that very concern when seeking a Lowell Institute public lec-
tureship by assuring the or ga nizer, “I can safely say that I am neither a ma-
terialistic partisan nor a spiritualistic bigot.” 14 Indeed. And he never did
choose a side or even just try to balance their contrasts. He recognized that
science and religion, which respectively contribute discovery of facts and
sustaining of hope, manifest in divergent ways, energize many diff er ent fields,
and have been used to support diverse values; and yet he detected that these
distinct enterprises make common attempts to identify the elusive qualities
of nature and offer guidance through lived experience.
As James noticed in his own experience and in theory, science and reli-
gion ask similar types of questions about the identity and character of the
world and humanity, even as they generally provide diff er ent answers—
answers that, at diff er ent times, for diff er ent people, and with se lection of
diff er ent parts of the complexities, gravitate toward or away from each
other. William James grew up with an early form of spirituality from his
father, but he would come to doubt the elder James’s absolutist confidence
and instead rely more deeply on science, absorbing its naturalism but also
questioning its own claims to certainty. This comfort with uncertainty ap-
pears biographically by the end of his young adulthood when he fi nally felt
ready to accept life “without any guarantee,” and it would become a central
feature of later theories in his commitment to genuine novelty. This orienta-
tion shows the importance of mystery for James, with kinship both to ancient
apophatic traditions, in their emphasis on silence and committed action
without waiting for certainty because so many topics remain steadily beyond
human understanding, and to Charles Peirce’s argument for the operation
of chance that he called the tychistic character of the world. James general-
ized on his commitment to uncertainty and mystery by maintaining that
“novelty . . . leaks in[to] experience, . . . with continuous infiltration of other-
ness.” This orientation shaped his approach to affirming “the validity of
possibility” in the many fields he experienced and studied. 15 And this open-
ness to otherness spilled beyond his philosophizing into his social thought.
James’s intellectual openness to uncertainties and his inquisitiveness
also drove him to support those out of power. This included an impulse to
“succor the underdog” that drew him to value people most others dismissed
as eccentrics, and it would also make him a resource for promotion of gen-
der and racial inclusion, even beyond the social steps he himself took. In his
own time, James pushed publicly for positions more progressive on race
Almost a Phi los o pher 17
than he was witnessing around him, with his agitation against lynching,
against anti- Semitism in the Dreyfus affair, and against American domination
of the Philippines. Yet he harbored many mainstream racial assumptions, in-
cluding patronizing views of nonwhites and ste reo typed perceptions of
Jews; on initial encounter, he could speak with a bluntness typical of the time,
especially when his “organ of perception- of- national- differences” was in a
“super- excited state.” These comments, crude by twenty- first- century stan-
dards, were not instead of his re spect and curiosity but a step in expressing
them. In the language of later years, his multiculturalism endorsed differ-
ence; or, to use his term from the end of his life, he urged embrace of “plu-
ralism.” His curiosity would draw him in, with pluralism as his theory for
“perception- of-[intellectual]- differences,” and then he invariably found im-
pressive qualities in the heart of otherness— and then he referred to those
qualities with casual directness. More simply, he firmly believed what
he blurted out in 1867, “Men differ, thank Heaven.” Witness his comfortable
and even enthusiastic relations with his African American student W. E. B.
Du Bois, who remembered, “I was repeatedly a guest in the home of William
James; he was my friend and guide to clear thinking.” For all his progres-
sive impulses, James maintained views of race soaked in the culture— and
the language—of his time. In one of his first essays, James relays a story of
a missionary in Africa eager to “dissuade the savage from his fetichistic [ sic]”
healing practices; to this, James pres ents the “savage” responding coyly, “[I]t
is just the same with [Western] doctors; you give your remedies, and some-
times the patient gets well and sometimes he dies.” James did not balk at
the patronizing language; and yet, even after earning his mainstream medi-
cal degree, he welcomed the African’s approach to healing in support of his
own medical pluralism. In addition, he supported the African’s “proverbial
philosophy” as “no . . . perverse act of thought”; such thoughts may be incom-
plete, but so too are even the most sophisticated and scientific propositions.16
Even though James blurted out his enthusiasm that “[m]en differ,” he
acted with ambivalence about whether such pluralistic recognition could
include women. He was torn between his ac cep tance of separate spheres
from his upbringing through his own marriage and his avid impulses for
pluralism and reform. So, while he felt a “presumption from use against”
women’s equality, he welcomed women’s achievements and even antici-
pated ele ments of difference feminism in his observations that women
“seize on particulars,” which coincided with his commitment to concrete
facts for puncturing the pretentions of abstract absolutes. James’s mixed
18 Young William James Thinking
rec ord on the cultural diversity of his time has inspired a similarly mixed
reading of his legacy for support of identity politics in own our time. Some
evaluations of James critique his limited actions against social and institu-
tional barriers to racial and gender equality in his own time, including in
his own everyday life; but others praise him for his recognition of the way
social contexts shape knowledge, a first step in challenging social hierar-
chies, and for his own contributions with progressive defiance of intellectu-
ally conventional and absolutist norms. James at once lived the prejudices
of his time and announced theories that promote equity. And more: he did
not just tolerate difference but lauded its potential to shake up convention
with innovative insight; he even named his alternative interests “feminine-
mystical” in contrast with his own “scientific- academic” training. His sup-
porters provide, in effect, a James upgraded for con temporary culture, a
cultural theory James, a James 2.0. The use of his thought and life as re-
sources for healing assumptions of racial and gender hierarchy carries
forward his own ambivalence from tension between his contexts and his ea-
gerness for change. James’s readiness to see both sides and his ambivalence
show that his relational thinking, when applied to social issues, prompted
him not only to pay attention to contrasting views but also to see the short-
comings of each— and so, ultimately, their need for each other. This shows
the depths of his readiness to live without guarantee, and it also indicates
that his uncertainties, enlisted as resources for working toward future im-
provements, could include a wide swath of perspectives, even while steer-
ing him away from quick fixes. Instead, this posture, which he would call
“meliorism,” would promote gradual efforts toward improvement. What his
perspective lacks for action on immediate change, it gains in inclusiveness
of diff er ent points of view. 17
James first embraced novelties when he encountered deep dimensions of
human consciousness during his educational development. Most religious
believers, especially those hewing to traditions about divine depths, avoided
psychological depths, and pioneers in the science of mind maintained a nat-
uralistic focus with little attention to religion; however, in subconscious
realms of mind, in these profound human experiences, which he under-
stood as win dows to nature, James found both spiritual and empirical sig-
nificance. From these perspectives, he took the task of mediation in science
and religion beyond compromise and tolerance, although he supported
such enterprises for their encouragement of communication and openness
to divergent commitments. Such moderate steps, however, did not touch on
Almost a Phi los o pher 19
the depths of potential connection he perceived to lurk within scientific and
religious enterprises and related fields. In our own time, despite more than
a generation of studies repudiating the supposed warfare of science and re-
ligion, widespread assumptions persist that these fields are irreconcilably
in conflict, or that they require thorough reconciliation— positions that do
not challenge the assumption of their fundamental differences. 18 James’s
biography and theories suggest another way.
James did not set immaterial (or apparently immaterial) ele ments in
psy chol ogy, philosophy, and spirituality against empiricism or scientific in-
quiry and their profound social impacts, in subordination to them, or even
alongside them. Instead, he thought of them operating through these worldly
paths, ideas that in his maturity would be called panpsychic theories of
mind in body, suggesting panentheist theories of spirituality within nature,
and ideas that in later years would establish him as a precursor to nondualist
theories of embodied mind and somaesthetics. In his own scientific re-
search and with his spiritual sensibilities developed in relation to his father
and his own avocational interests, James detected the significance of imma-
terial ele ments of life embedded within the material world, before he developed
formal theoretical labels for these ideas. Human hopes, volitions, motiva-
tions, ideals, thoughts, assumptions, faith, beliefs, convictions, feelings, per-
sonal energy, and the spark of life itself seem unempirical and may very well
connect to abstract dimensions or even another world, but in our experi-
ence of them, he maintained, these are fully part of nature. With this orien-
tation, James adapts his father’s view of “inward being,” which gives the
“spiritual lift” to humans in their “spiritual existence” within their “natu-
ral existence.” This view of spiritual or psychological dynamism circulating
in natu ral matter both follows in the wake of Baruch Spinoza’s and Sweden-
borg’s references to “conatus,” the living “endeavor” from the “interiors of
the mind” striving for power and meaning, and anticipates what a con-
temporary neuroscientist has called the “life pro cess.” Antonio Damasio
defines conatus in scientific terms as “the aggregate of dispositions laid
down by brain circuitry that, once engaged by internal and environmental
conditions, seeks both survival and well- being”; he treats conatus as an old
term for modern research proj ects on the “mystery” of “conscious minds
working” within “aggregates called tissues.” From his youth, William James
likewise maintained that the sciences are essential tools for understanding
the character and natu ral operations of these vivid but often intangible parts
of human life— even if scientific investigations are not themselves capable of
20 Young William James Thinking
final answers. His commitment to the intertwining of material and imma-
terial factors would appear throughout his work in his insistence on the
simultaneous physiology and feelings of emotion, his study of humanity’s
embodied will, his scrutiny of human nature within evaluation of religion,
his analy sis of simultaneous objectivity and subjectivity in “pure experience”
so often separated for vari ous “temporary purposes,” and his pragmatic
recognition of the human “hankering for the good things” of both empirical
and rational thinking.19 The disarming frankness of his reports from expe-
rience has been a key to his ability to gain ac cep tance, and even popularity,
despite his unorthodox mingling of science and religion, and other realms
that conventionally remain far apart.
Much attention to James has grown from the sheer variety of his work,
which has prompted investigators from diff er ent fields to evaluate him us-
ing the tools of many disciplines. He is a significant figure in many branches
of philosophy, intellectual and cultural history, history of science, psy chol-
ogy, neuroscience, depth psy chol ogy intersecting with spirituality, religious
studies, rhe toric, and even cultural studies and lit er a ture. He was a protean
figure working before many of these disciplines had formed, often pointing
in the directions that they would take— and even toward paths not yet
taken. Commentaries on James from the disciplines of his contributions
have been abundant and rich, but they generally have had little contact with
each other. Aspects of James covered by diff er ent disciplines have led to
puzzlement or selective disregard— just as his psy chol ogy of attention for-
mation would predict—as if his integration of diverse interests was simply a
marvel largely beyond explanation. There has been much smiling admira-
tion for James, less as a founding father of par tic u lar schools of thought
than as an avuncular figure admired by many. 20 This place of honor has
ironically undercut the ability to learn from some of his most impor tant and
helpful insights; it effectively lets each field adopt its piece of James without
attention to the rest.
The interdisciplinary work of Miles Orvell provides a helpful meta phor
for steering through diff er ent approaches: perspectives focusing on parts,
each impor tant, can remain vertical views, “in isolation,” until attending to
their connections horizontally, as “parts of a larger whole.” Interpretations
reflect their times; today, interpretation includes the power of specialized
discourse. Many of these deep yet selective treatments arrive at James from
the lens of their own disciplines and even echo the perceived warfare of sci-
ence and religion. For example, some commentators examine his philosoph-
Almost a Phi los o pher 21
ical naturalism or his anticipation of other par tic u lar topics in philosophy or
psy chol ogy but find his religious interests, much less his psychical research
or study of sectarian medicine and depth consciousness, peculiar or eccen-
tric distractions. By contrast, religious studies commentators discern his
readiness to support belief and diverse religious experiences but pay little
attention to his scientific training and commitments. The disciplinary affili-
ations of the interpreters add weight to the differences, and their academic
separation keeps each domain distinct, because of the tendency within pro-
fessions, as James himself predicted, for “institutionalizing on a large scale
to run into technicality.” 21 Modern scholarship encourages each point of
view, emerging from its respective discipline, to be presented as the crucial
ele ment for understanding James, even though he himself did not think in
these terms. Despite these limitations, the specialized work of the past few de-
cades has also produced more understanding than we have ever known before.
The more “horizontal” approach of this book, connecting phases of James’s
life and his diff er ent fields of study, especially as his commitments were coming
into formation, can show the relations of previous interpretations—and the re-
lations among his intellectual proj ects— with potential to complement and
build on them.
This work of developmental biography pursues James’s experiences
through youthful texts and contexts to illuminate his intentions and directions
on paths toward his mature theories. This method displays a surface resem-
blance to the work of Erik Erikson; rather than focus on mature work, the
end points of a subject’s career, he proposed “originology, . . . which reduces
every human to an analogy with an earlier one, and most of all to that earliest,
simplest, and most infantile precursor which is assumed to be its ‘origin.’ ”